Abortion advocates from both the Religious Coalition for Reproductive
Choice and Planned Parenthood Federation of America contend that the
Bible is silent on abortion. None of the Scriptures traditionally cited
by pro‐life advocates establish the humanity of the unborn, they
proclaim. “One thing the Bible does not say is ‘Thou shalt not abort,’”
writes Roy Bowen Ward, professor emeritus of comparative religion at
Miami University of Ohio.1 Reverend Mark Bigelow, a member of Planned
Parenthood’s Clergy Advisory Board, writes, “Even as a minister I am
careful what I presume Jesus would do if he were alive today, but one
thing I know from the Bible is that Jesus was not against women having a
choice in continuing a pregnancy. He never said a word about abortion
(nor did anyone else in the Bible) even though abortion was available
and in use in his time.”2 Paul D. Simmons, former professor of Christian
ethics at Southern Baptist Theological Seminary, finds the Bible’s
silence on abortion “profound” and remarks that not once does the
subject appear in any of the apostle Paul’s lists of prohibited
actions.3 Suppose we grant that Ward, Bigelow, and Simmons are correct
in that the Bible is silent on abortion. Let’s further suppose that none
of the specified passages cited by pro‐life advocates (Ps. 51:5;
139:13–15; and Luke 1:41–44 to name a few) explicitly say the unborn are
human. Does it follow, therefore, that Scripture teaches that women
have a God‐given right to abort their unborn offspring? The purpose of
this article is to show that the case for elective abortion based on the
alleged silence of Scripture is flawed both theologically and
philosophically.
DOES SILENCE EQUAL PERMISSION?
Abortion
advocates are correct that the Bible does not specifically mention
abortion, but what’s the best explanation for its silence? The hidden
(and undefended) premise in the argument advanced by Ward, Bigelow, and
Simmons is that whatever the Bible doesn’t condemn it condones. It’s
easy to see that this premise is flawed, since it leads to some absurd
conclusions. The Bible does not expressly condemn many things, including
racial discrimination against blacks, killing abortion doctors as a
means of fighting abortion, and lynching homosexuals, and yet few people
would argue that these acts are morally justified. We know, in fact,
that they are wrong by inference. Scripture, for example, tells us it’s
wrong to treat human beings unjustly. Lynching homosexuals treats human
beings unjustly. Scripture, therefore, condemns this activity even if
the topic of lynching is never explicitly addressed. A century ago,
racists argued from the alleged silence of Scripture that blacks were
not human. Some went so far as to deny that blacks had souls.4 This
argument was hardly persuasive. Scripture does not mention every
specific race and nationality, but it does teach that all humans are
made in God’s image and were created to have fellowship with Him (Gen.
1:26; Gal. 3:28; Col. 3:10–11). The inference is clear: if blacks are
human beings, they, too, are made in God’s image. No further proof from
Scripture is necessary. As we shall see, the same is true with the
unborn. If embryos and fetuses are human beings, then biblical commands
that forbid the unjust taking of human life apply to them as they do to
other humans. Appealing to the Bible’s alleged silence on abortion
misses the point entirely. That is why when abortion advocates argue
their case from the silence of Scripture, I ask, “Are you saying that
whenever the Bible does not specifically condemn something, it condones
it?” When they say no (and they must), I reply, “Then what is your
point?” Contrary to Ward and Bigelow, there are good reasons to suppose
the alleged silence of Scripture does not mean the biblical writers
condoned abortion, but that prohibitions against it were largely
unnecessary. We should remember that the Bible as a whole is not a
comprehensive code of ethics; rather, the Bible is the story of God’s
redemption of His people. In other words, the biblical writers, under
guidance from the Holy Spirit, selectively discussed topics relevant to
their intended audiences while leaving many other topics unstated. If
neither the Hebrews of the Old Testament nor the Christians of the New
Testament were inclined to abort their unborn offspring, there was
little reason for the biblical writers to address the matter. The Old
Testament Context Biblical and cultural evidence suggests that the
original audiences of the Bible were not inclined to consider abortion
even though it was practiced in surrounding cultures.5 Turning first to
the Hebrew worldview found in the Old Testament, we find that: • Humans
have intrinsic value because they are made in the image of God. The
shedding of innocent blood is hence strictly forbidden (Gen. 1:26; 9:6;
Exod. 23:7; Prov. 6:16–17). • Children are seldom seen as unwanted or as
a nuisance (unless they turn wicked), but they are considered gifts
from God — the greatest possible blessings (Ps. 127:3–5; 113:9; cf. Gen.
17:6; 33:5). • Immortality is expressed through one’s descendants. God
promised Abraham to make of him a great nation and that promise was
passed on to Isaac, Jacob, and so on. “Sons are a heritage from the
Lord, children a reward from him,” wrote the psalmist (Ps. 127:3; cf.
Gen. 48:16). • Sterility and barrenness are a curse, a source of great
shame and sorrow. Peninnah therefore harshly ridiculed Hannah, the
prophet Samuel’s mother, because of the latter’s initial barrenness (1
Sam. 1:6; cf. Gen. 20:17–18; 30:1, 22–23). As theologian Germain Grisez
points out, among a people who saw children as a gift and barrenness as a
curse, it was unthinkable that an Israelite woman should desire an
abortion. In such a context, the Old Testament’s silence on abortion
suggests that prohibitions against it were largely unnecessary and not
that the practice was tacitly approved.
Ward disputes this
conclusion, noting it was common for authors of both Testaments to
condemn the practices of neighboring nations, “such as idol worship,
sacred prostitution, and the like, yet they did not choose to condemn
abortion” — a practice common in those surrounding cultures.7 Ward’s
rejoinder, however, is not persuasive. Unlike abortion, idolatrous
practices were not restricted to neighboring cultures, but at times were
pervasive among God’s own people; indeed, Ward overlooks the fact that
Israel and Judah were taken captive on numerous occasions precisely
because of their idolatry (Ps. 106:35–43; Jer. 1:16; 2:23; Ezek.
6:1–10). It is no surprise, therefore, that the biblical writers
mentioned this practice but not abortion; although Israel’s neighboring
cultures practiced abortion, it does not mean the Hebrews practiced
abortion as well. In short, Ward fails to interpret the Old Testament
within its own intellectual and historical‐cultural framework. Ward’s
argument from silence, moreover, implies too much. The Bible does not
mention one of the most heinous practices of the surrounding ancient
world, female infanticide, but it does not follow from this that the act
is therefore morally justified. The view that the absence of a direct
prohibition meant that women had a God‐given right to kill their
offspring would have been utterly foreign to the Hebrew culture of the
time. The New Testament Context Abortion was a foreign thought in the
New Testament as well. Professor Michael J. Gorman writes that the first
Christians were largely Jewish, with an essentially Jewish morality.8
If a Jewish consensus against abortion existed at the time, the early
Christians most certainly would have shared that consensus. As Gorman
points out, first‐century Judaism was, in fact, quite firmly opposed to
abortion. Jewish documents from the period condemn the practice
unequivocally, demonstrating a clear antiabortion consensus among Jews: •
The Sentences of Pseudo‐Phocylides (written between 50 bc and ad 50)
says, “A woman should not destroy the unborn babe in her belly, nor
after its birth throw it before the dogs and vultures.” • The Sibyline
Oracles includes among the wicked those who “produce abortions and
unlawfully cast their offspring away.” Also condemned are sorcerers who
dispense abortifacients (an abortion‐inducing substance or device). •
First Enoch (a first or second century bc document) says an evil angel
taught humans how to “smash the embryo in the womb.” Josephus (a
first‐century Jewish historian) stated, “The law orders all the
offspring be brought up, and forbids women either to cause abortion or
to make away with the fetus.” A woman who did so was considered to have
committed infanticide because she destroyed a “soul” and hence
diminished the race.9 These texts, writes Gorman, “bear witness to the
general Jewish and Jewish‐Christian attitude of the first and second
centuries, thus confirming that the earliest Christians shared the
anti‐abortion position of their Jewish forebears.”10 Finally, we should
remember that the theology of the New Testament epistles is primarily
“task” theology written to address specific issues in specific churches.
Paul, for example, is largely silent on the historical career of Christ
(he mentions it only in passing while underscoring the importance of
the Resurrection in 1 Corinthians 15), but this does not mean that he
questioned the facts of Jesus’ earthly ministry. A discussion of those
facts simply never became necessary. New Testament scholar George Eldon
Ladd stated, “We may say that we owe whatever understanding we have of
Paul’s thought to the ‘accidents of history’ which required him to deal
with various problems, doctrinal and practical, in the life of the
churches.”11 The best explanation, then, for the New Testament’s silence
on abortion is not that its authors condoned the practice, but that a
discussion of the issue was unnecessary. As Gorman points out, there was
no deviation from the norm inherited from Judaism. Unlike the
surrounding pagan cultures, the early Christians to whom the New
Testament was written were simply not inclined to kill their children
before or after birth.
WHAT IS THE UNBORN AND WHY SHOULD WE CARE?
The
morality of abortion comes down to just one question: Is the unborn a
member of the human family? If so, elective abortion is a serious moral
wrong that violates biblical commands against the unjust taking of human
life (Exod. 23:7; Ps. 106:37–38; Prov. 6:16–17; Matt. 5:21). It treats
the unborn human being, made in the image of God (Gen. 1:26; 9:6; James
3:9), as nothing more than disposable tissue. Conversely, if the unborn
are not human, elective abortion requires no more justification than
having a tooth pulled. Scripture (we will grant) is silent on the
humanity of the unborn (as it is on the humanity of whites, blacks,
Asians, etc.); however, it is clear that we are not to take human life
without justification. It follows that if a positive case can be made
for the humanity of the unborn apart from Scripture (as, e.g., we know
the French are humans apart from Scripture), we can logically conclude
that biblical commands against the unjust taking of human life apply to
the unborn as they do other human beings. At this point, science assists
theology; that is to say, science gives us the facts we need to arrive
at a theologically sound conclusion. What the facts of science make
clear is that from the earliest stages of development, the unborn are
distinct, living, and whole human beings. True, they have yet to grow
and mature, but they are whole human beings nonetheless. Leading
embryology textbooks affirm this conclusion.12 An Embryo Is More than
Human Cells Abortion advocate Virginia Ramey Mollenkott, whose work is
prominently featured in the literature of the Religious Coalition for
Reproductive Choice, insists, however, that we gain no theological
knowledge from these facts. “The fetus is biologically human only in the
sense that any part of a human body is human: every cell carries the
full genetic code. A severed hand is genetically human as well but we
don’t call it a person.”13 In other words, Mollenkott would have us
believe there is no difference in kind between a human embryo and each
of our cells. This is bad biology. Mollenkott is making the rather
elementary mistake of confusing parts with wholes. The difference in
kind between each of our cells and a human embryo is clear: an
individual cell’s functions are subordinated to the survival of the
larger organism of which it is merely a part. The human embryo, however,
is already a whole human entity. Robert George and Patrick Lee argue
that it makes no sense to say you were once a sperm or somatic cell when
science clearly states that you were once a human embryo: “Somatic
cells are not, and embryonic human beings are, distinct,
self‐integrating organisms capable of directing their own maturation as
members of the human species.”14 Maureen Condic, assistant professor of
neurobiology and anatomy at the University of Utah, points out that
embryos are living human beings “precisely because they possess the
single defining feature of human life that is lost in the moment of
death — the ability to function as a coordinated organism rather than
merely as a group of living human cells.” Condic explains the important
distinction between individual body parts and whole human embryos
overlooked by Mollenkott: “The critical difference between a collection
of cells and a living organism is the ability of an organism to act in a
coordinated manner for the continued health and maintenance of the body
as a whole. It is precisely this ability that breaks down at the moment
of death, however death might occur. Dead bodies may have plenty of
live cells, but their cells no longer function together in a coordinated
manner.”15 From conception forward, human embryos clearly function as
organisms. “Embryos are not merely collections of human cells, but
living creatures with all the properties that define any organism as
distinct from a group of cells; embryos are capable of growing,
maturing, maintaining a physiologic balance between various organ
systems, adapting to changing circumstances, and repairing injury. Mere
groups of human cells [e.g., a severed hand] do nothing like this under
any circumstances.”16
WHAT MAKES HUMANS VALUABLE?
Do
humans come to be at one point, but come to be valuable only later by
virtue of some acquired property (i.e., characteristic)? In his article,
“Personhood, the Bible, and the Abortion Debate,” Paul D.
Simmons
concedes that zygotes (early embryos) are biologically human, but he
denies they are “complex” or “developed enough” to qualify as “persons”
in a biblical sense. “No one can deny the continuum from fertilization
to maturity and adulthood,” writes Simmons. “That does not mean,
however, that every step on the continuum has the same value or
constitutes the same entity.”17 Simmons’s larger purpose is to defend
abortion rights by telling us who does and does not bear God’s image. He
argues that humans bear that image (and hence, have value as “persons”)
not by virtue of the kind of thing they are (members of a natural kind
or species), but only because of an acquired property, in this case, the
immediate capacity for self‐awareness. A “person,” he contends, “has
capacities of reflective choice, relational responses, social
experience, moral perception, and self‐awareness.”18 Zygotes, as mere
clusters of human cells, do not have this capacity and therefore do not
bear God’s image. Three counterexamples underscore the arbitrary nature
of Simmons’s claim. First, newborns cannot make conscious, reflective
choices until several months after birth.19 What principled reason,
therefore, can Simmons give for saying infanticide is wrong? Peter
Singer points out in Practical Ethics that if self‐ awareness makes one
valuable as a person, and newborns like fetuses lack that property, it
follows that both fetus and newborn are disqualified. One cannot
arbitrary draw a line at birth to spare the newborn.20 Abraham Lincoln
raised a similar point with slavery, noting that any argument used to
disqualify blacks as valuable human beings works equally well to
disqualify whites: You say “A” is white and “B” is black. It is color,
then: the lighter having the right to enslave the darker? Take care. By
this rule, you are a slave to the first man you meet with a fairer skin
than your own. You do not mean color exactly — You mean the whites are
intellectually the superiors of the blacks, and therefore have the right
to enslave them? Take care again: By this rule you are to be a slave to
the first man you meet with an intellect superior to your own. But you
say it is a question of interest, and, if you can make it your interest,
you have the right to enslave another. Very well. And if he can make it
his interest, he has the right to enslave you.21 In short, Simmons
cannot account for basic human equality. As George and Lee point out, if
humans are valuable only because of some acquired property such as skin
color or self‐awareness and not in virtue of the kind of thing they
are, then it follows that since these acquired properties come in
varying degrees, basic human rights also come in varying degrees. Do we
really want to say that those with more self‐ awareness are more human
(and more valuable) than those with less? This relegates the proposition
“all men and women are created equal” to the ash heap of history.22
Theologically, it’s far more reasonable to argue that although humans
differ immensely with respect to talents, accomplishments, and degrees
of development (acquired properties), they are nonetheless equally
valuable because they have in common a nature made in God’s image.
Humans are equally valuable by virtue of being equally human. Second, if
the immediate capacity for consciousness makes one valuable, many
nonhuman animals qualify as persons. This is Peter Singer’s point.
Singer contends that a variety of nonhuman animals are rational,
self‐conscious beings that qualify as persons in the relevant sense of
the term; consequently, dogs, cats, and pigs are valuable persons, while
fetuses, newborns, and victims of Alzheimer’s disease are not. Singer
concludes that to favor the preconscious infant over a self‐conscious
dog simply because the infant is biologically human makes one guilty of
“speciesism,” a crime akin to racism.23 It’s hard to see how Simmons can
escape this same conclusion given his belief that God’s image in humans
is grounded in the property of self‐awareness per se rather than in
human nature, which allows for self‐consciousness among other
capacities, given the right conditions. Third, human embryos have a
basic (root) capacity for self‐consciousness, lacking only the
immediate, or current, capacity for it. As George points out, human
embryos possess this basic capacity by virtue of the kind of thing they
are — members of a natural kind, a biological species — whose members
(if not prevented by some extrinsic cause) in due course develop the
immediate capacity for such mental acts.24 We can, therefore,
distinguish between two types of capacities for mental functions: (1)
basic, or natural, and (2) immediate, or current. On what basis can
Simmons require for the recognition of full moral respect the second
sort of capacity, which is an accidental (i.e., nonessential) attribute,
and not the first, which is grounded in the kind of thing one is?25 I
cannot think of any basis that is not arbitrary. One grows in the
ability to perform mental acts only because one already is the kind of
thing that grows into the ability to perform mental acts, that is, a
human being. My thoughts and my feelings, indeed all of my functional
mental abilities, cannot exist unless I first exist. I can exist without
them, as, for example, when I am sleeping, but they cannot exist
without me.26 In the end, Simmons’s case for human value is ad hoc and
arbitrary. It cannot answer why self‐awareness is the biblically
relevant factor rather than another, nor why a certain level of
development is necessary.
FLAWED THEOLOGY
Exodus
21:22–25 is a favorite of abortion advocates, though it does little to
bolster their case. The passage reads in the nasb as follows: “And if
men struggle with each other and strike a woman with child so that she
has a miscarriage [“gives birth prematurely” in nasb 1995 update], yet
there is no further injury, he shall surely be fined as the woman’s
husband may demand of him; and he shall pay as the judges decide. But if
there is any further injury, then you shall appoint as a penalty life
for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth, hand for hand, foot for foot,
burn for burn, wound for wound, bruise for bruise.” Abortion advocates
argue that this Scripture proves the unborn are not fully human because
the penalty for accidentally killing a fetus is less than the penalty
for killing its mother. This argument, however, is flawed on several
counts. First, assuming for the sake of argument that the pro‐abortion
interpretation of this passage is correct (i.e., that the unborn’s death
is treated differently from the mother’s), it still does not follow
that the unborn are not fully human. The preceding verses (21:20–21)
present a situation where a master unintentionally kills his slave and
escapes with no penalty at all (the lack of intent being proven by the
interval between the blow and the death), and yet it hardly follows that
Scripture considers the slave less than human. Second, this passage
does not even remotely suggest that a woman can willfully kill her
unborn child through elective abortion. Nothing in the context supports
this claim. At best, the text assigns a lesser penalty for accidentally
killing a fetus than for accidentally killing its mother. It simply does
not follow from this that a woman may deliberately kill her child
through abortion. Third, the pro‐abortion interpretation of this passage
(that a lesser penalty applies for accidental fetal death) is highly
questionable. When read in the original Hebrew, the passage seems to
convey that both the mother and the child are covered by the lex
talionis — the law of retribution. According to Hebrew scholar Gleason
Archer, “There is no second class status attached to the fetus under
this [lex talionis] rule. The fetus is just as valuable as the
mother.”27 Taken together, the cultural, exegetical, philosophical, and
scientific considerations we’ve examined prove that the Bible need not
explicitly say elective abortion is wrong before we can know it is
wrong. Although the Bible does not say “Thou shalt not abort,” it does
prohibit the unjust taking of human life, which applies to the unborn as
it does to other humans.
No comments:
Post a Comment